Sunday, September 05, 2004

Political points or arguments ?

Doc, Thanks for your comment yesterday. I am eagerly awaiting your monday reply. In the meantime, I would just like to share a few thoughts that came to my mind while reading one of your sentences.

You say your impression is that 'the Logical Positivists were largely successful in their arguments, but were unable to score [...] political points'. Naturally, I have exactly the opposite one ! Like so often in a debate between two sincerely held, but widely differing, positions, I have this strange feeling that we are not living in the same world. It seems we are on opposites sides of the mirror : at least one of us is in wonderland.

My own opinion on this matter has been formed quite recently, actually, while reading about Logical Positivism from various sources, some of which I already cited here. All describe the Vienna circle as a closly knit and very industrious group, deliberatly engaged in an energetic effort to popularize their ideas. Says O. Hanfling (Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy) :

International conferences were called with a view to disseminating the new 'insights', and a grandiose project, The Encyclopedia of Unified Science, was launched to give definitive expression to the new `scientific' era in which philosophical and other discourse would become part of the discourse of science.
A similar account can be found in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy article on the Vienna Circle :
The Vienna Circle was very active in advertising the new philosophical ideas of logical positivism. Several congresses on epistemology and philosophy of science were organized, with the help of the Berlin Circle. There were some preparatory congresses: Prague (1929), Könisberg (1930), Prague (1934) and then the first congress on scientific philosophy held in Paris (1935), followed by congresses in Copenhagen (1936), Paris (1937), Cambridge, England (1938), Cambridge, Mass. (1939).
In another paper (H. Feigl & al. Homage to R. Carnap, 1970), I found the following description of one of the proceedings of the Circle in the 1920s :
I remember vividly Carnap's first lecture (1925) to the Vienna Circle. He presented his Space-Time topology [...] in the manner an engineer might explain the structure of a machine he had just invented. To the non-logicians Carnap indeed seemed to be no philosopher at all.
The reference to an engineer strikes me as a sign of the times. 'Ingenieurs', as they were called both in German and French, were popular then. They seemed to be the wave of the future and that nothing could resist them. This was the era of the Ford Model T, Charlie Chaplin's Modern Times, the peak of the railroads and of electrification. In a word, Logical Positivism was in sync with the trends of its time, and, indeed, many described it as a new fashionable creed that was sweeping the younger strata of the philosophy, mathematics and science departments.

Echoing this, the tone of the article opposing Logical Positivism published, while it was in full swing, is defensive, but respectful :

'[The] views of [LP] compels us to reexamine the foundations of knowledge and the grounds of validity, the Viennese synthesis should be welcomed as a challenge to all traditional points of view.'

WH Werkmeister "Seven theses of Logical Positivism Critically Examined", The Philosophical Review, 1937.

Some years later, it becomes almost desperate :

"THE most obvious general feature of current philosophy is a negative one, and this is its determined effort to repudiate metaphysics. [...] On this topic professionals and laymen agree; and logical positivists, pragmatists, Cambridge analysts, operationalists, American naturalists, semanticists, and even self-confessed nominalists join hands with political radicals and successful business men in condemning as unnecessary [...] the study of metaphysics."

JK. Feibleman, "A Defense of Ontology", The Journal of Philosophy, 1949.

So, apparently, at the turn of the 1940s and 1950s, Logical Positivism seemed successful; the victorious avant-garde of a host of other philosophical schools. Note that in the example above, the repudiation of metaphysics is described as a general feature of current philosophy. In the eyes of the author, it is the dominant, mainstream view. Is not this situation to be considered a 'political' victory for Logical Positivism in the philosophical arena ?

Then, in the 1950s and 60s, the tides turned and Logical Positivism was thoroughly routed and AJ. Ayer driven to confess defeat as stated earlier. What matters are the reasons for this defeat and, again, we are here at the heart of the matter. Almost all recent accounts of the history of philosophy cite technical reasons : LP was defeated because its argument failed to stand up to criticism.

While, still recently, I had only vague notions about LP, these are the data out of which which I built the impression that LP was a once politically dominant movement in philosophy that eventually collapsed because its argument were not technically waterproof. But again, on a deeper level, I am convinced there is more to it than that.

2 Comments:

At September 6, 2004 at 1:37 PM, Blogger Doctor Logic said...

Nicolas,

First, here are my political points.

I agree that LP had a major impact on philosophy, and that it was probably dominant (at the level of research) at one point.

But why did LP lose its influence in professional circles? Is metaphysics still alive in academic research around the world? If so, is metaphysics to philosophy what creationism is to evolutionary biology?

There are analogues in physics: models that showed great promise, but which were later bogged-down with complexities that made them unattractive. Superstring theory is one of them (though, ironically, superstring theory is now making a comeback). String theory was just taking hold when I was an undergraduate student. String theory's big idea was this: what if you could only create one unique, consistent theory of everything? If we could find that one theory mathematically, then we could short-circuit the normal scientific research process. In one stroke, we could leap to the top of the pyramid and derive all the physics we wanted to. Unfortunately, string theory turned out not to be unique. It was also quite complex, and getting measurable predictions from the theory was very difficult. After years of theoretical research, there wasn't much to show the experimentalists. By the time I left graduate school, superstring theory was thought to be dying out.

My sense is that LP is viewed in the philosophy community the way string theory is viewed by the physics community. Namely, a theory that showed a lot of promise, but which was bogged-down with complexities. Of course, my not being part of the philosophy community, this is hard for me to judge with any accuracy.

Should we expect philosophical research to drive aspects of human social development? As with science, knowledge of philosophy is considered optional for the layperson. Only a very small number of laypeople have even heard of logical positivism or logical empiricism. If LP had been unambiguously victorious, would its tenets have been promulgated to the masses?

I fear not. After all, almost 45% of Americans believe in creationism. I guess reality just doesn't catch up with some people.

doctor(logic)

 
At September 6, 2004 at 2:14 PM, Blogger Doctor Logic said...

Nicolas,

Here is my present thinking on logical empiricism.

Where did this come from? It is a mix of logical empiricist doctrine and my own understanding of scientific research.

I know that Carnap, Reichenbach and von Mises devoted a lot of attention to scientific method, attempting to narrow the method either to a deductive scheme or to an inductive one. I thought these schemes were unnecessarily rigid and possibly superfluous.

The following are my definitions and interpretations:

Logic. The function of logic is to determine whether a given set of propositions can be assigned a corresponding set of truth values without contradiction.

If we reject logic, we must accept that a proposition P and its negation ~P may both be simultaneously true.

Mathematics. Mathematics is derived from logic using a set of axiomatic propositions. There are many variations of mathematics, each one founded on a particular set of axioms or assumptions (e.g., Euclidean vs. non-Euclidean Geometry?).

Observations. We make observations of the world that consist of sense data.

Modeling. We cannot "understand" observational data without making correlations between different observations. Even historical facts about the world could not be understood without these correlations, because time (as a position) itself is an observable.

In order to correlate observations, we create mathematical models (also known as theories) that order the observations, and that predict new observations or explain existing ones.

Model Non-uniqueness. In general, the number of mathematical models consistent with a finite number of observations at a given precision is infinite. Therefore, any mathematical model that correlates our finite number of observations is not unique.

Science. The role of science is to create, test and select mathematical models of observations.

Model Selection. Models are selected by their ability to explain past observations, their ability to predict new observations, their compatibility with existing models, and by their economy. Two models are incompatible if they predict contradictory observations. A model is economical if it makes predictions about observations that can be falsified with minimal experimental effort.

Completeness. A proposition is complete if it contains all the necessary assumptions and definitions that will make it a falsifiable model.

Natural Language. Natural language predominantly contains propositions that are incomplete. This is not necessarily a defect in natural language. If the incomplete propositions are used for the purpose of communicating facts between people with common models, then such natural language propositions are effective.

However, using the incomplete propositions of natural language to exchange facts between two people with different models is ineffective. Furthermore, incomplete propositions of natural language are not themselves models of observable phenomena.



It is my contention that this is a fairly minimal set of assumptions. It cleanly explains incomplete natural language propositions that people may otherwise "feel" are meaningful. As far as I can tell, it is also fully compatible with the scientific method.

Nicolas, you may have some objections to my definitions or my conclusions. Alternatively, you may simply not like the logical consequences of this philosophy (e.g., the resultant ethics).

In any case, I look forward to your response.

Regards,
doctor(logic)

 

Post a Comment

<< Home